The Christian Church has hitherto. . . [recognized] Christ as the one and only God-man.
But the indwelling of the Holy Ghost, the third Divine Person, in man, brings about a Christification of many, and the question then arises whether these many are all complete God-men. . . .
It is well to remind ourselves of St. Paul and his split consciousness: on one side he felt he was the apostle directly called and enlightened by God, and, on the other side, a sinful man who could not pluck out the “thorn in the flesh” and rid himself of the Satanic angel who plagued him.
That is to say even the enlightened person remains what he is, and is never more than his own limited ego before the One who dwells within him, whose form has no knowable boundaries, who encompasses him on all sides, fathomless as the abysms of the earth and vast as the sky.
~Carl Jung, CW 11, Page 470.
Wednesday, August 21, 2019
Carl Jung: …even the enlightened person remains what he is…
Can Neuroscience understand free will?
by Brian Gallagher
In The Good Place, a cerebral fantasy-comedy TV series, moral philosophy gets teased. On YouTube, the show released a promotional video, “This Is Why Everyone Hates Moral Philosophy,” that gets its title from a line directed at Chidi, a Senegalese professor of moral philosophy who suffers from chronic indecision: The pros and cons of even trivial choices have long paralyzed him. We see him, as a precocious boy, urged to get on with picking teammates for a soccer game. Flustered, Chidi explains, “I have to consider all the factors: athletic strategies, the fragile egos of my classmates, and gender politics! Should I pick a girl as a gesture toward women’s equality, or is that pandering? Or do I think it’s pandering because of my limited male point of view? I’m vexed!” The kids waiting to play shake their heads, facepalming. A friend later insists he “fix his brain.” An M.R.I., courtesy of a neuroscientist named Simone, shows he’s fine. “Wow, there are actual answers here—data you can observe, and learn from,” Chidi says. “Yeah, man! Science is all about getting answers,” Simone replies. “You philosophers can spend your entire life mulling over a single question. That’s why everyone hates moral philosophy professors.” Both of them chuckle and she adds, “No offense.”
This is mock-hate, born of love. Before Mike Schur, the show’s creator, started shooting scenes, he paid a visit to the UCLA moral philosopher Pamela Hieronymi for insight. She’s interested in the sort of control humans have over our intentions and emotions, and how it might differ from control over our actions. Her favorite thought experiment comes from a 1983 paper, “The Toxin Puzzle,” by Gregory Kavka. A delightful head-scratcher, it invites you to imagine that an eccentric billionaire has offered you a deal: If you merely intend to drink a toxin tonight, at midnight, that will make you painfully ill for a day, he will wire you a million dollars—it’ll be in your bank tomorrow morning. A sophisticated and reliable brain scanner will determine whether you really formed the intention to imbibe the toxin. After you have the funds in your bank account, you’re free to decide not to drink it. An easy way to become a millionaire, no? Just intend to drink it for the scanner and, once you have the cash, switch your intention.
The sense of freedom we have to act on our moral understanding is regulated and vulnerable, and can break.
This is absurd, of course, and that’s Kavka’s point: We don’t have that sort of control over ourselves. If you intend to drink it (for the sake of the scanner) but also intend, later, to not drink it (to avoid the sickness), you’re really intending to not drink it. Our intentions are only “partly volitional,” Kavka says. “One cannot intend whatever one wants to intend any more than one can believe whatever one wants to believe. As our beliefs are constrained by our evidence, so our intentions are constrained by our reasons for action.” The sense that you have of being in control, of having free will, is just that—a sense. And it can break.
Clinical neuroscientists and neurologists have identified the brain networks responsible for this sense of free will. There seems to be two: the network governing the desire to act, and the network governing the feeling of responsibility for acting. Brain-damaged patients show that these can come apart—you can have one without the other.
Lacking essentially all motivation to move or speak has a name: akinetic mutism. The researchers, lead by neurologists Michael Fox, of Harvard Medical School, and Ryan Darby, of Vanderbilt University, analyzed 28 cases of this condition, not all of them involving damage in the same departments. “We found that brain lesions that disrupt volition occur in many different locations, but fall within a single brain network, defined by connectivity to the anterior cingulate,” which has links to both the “emotional” limbic system and the “cognitive” prefrontal cortex, the researchers wrote. Feeling like you’re moving under the direction of outside forces has a name, too: alien limb syndrome. The researchers analyzed 50 cases of this condition, which again involved brain damage in different spots. “Lesions that disrupt agency also occur in many different locations, but fall within a separate network, defined by connectivity to the precuneus,” which is involved, among other things, in the experience of agency.
The results may not map onto “free will” as we understand it ethically—the ability to choose between right and wrong. “It remains unknown whether the network of brain regions we identify as related to free will for movements is the same as those important for moral decision-making, as prior studies have suggested important differences,” the researchers wrote. For instance, in a 2017 study, he and Darby analyzed many cases of brain lesions in various regions predisposing people to criminal behavior, and found that “these lesions all fall within a unique functionally connected brain network involved in moral decision making.”
Nevertheless, the fact that brain damage affects moral behavior only underscores the reality that, whatever the “will” is, it isn’t “free.” The sense of freedom we have to act on our moral understanding is regulated and vulnerable, and can break. In a 2016 paper, Darby noted that people who have behavioral-variant frontotemporal dementia “develop immoral behaviors as a result of their disease despite the ability to explicitly state that their behavior is wrong.” This complicates how moral responsibility should be understood, he explains. People can be capable of acknowledging wrongdoing and yet be incapable of acting accordingly. Responsibility can’t hinge on any simple notion of “reason responsiveness,” Darby says, which is a view of how free will can be compatible with determinism—the idea, in the case of behavior, that brain activity causes feelings, intentions, and actions, moral or not.
It’s still not clear whether lay people tend to lean toward “compatibilism” or not. Experimental philosophers have been trying to find out for years, but haven’t landed on a consensus. A recent study explains why: “People are strongly motivated to preserve free will and moral responsibility, and thus do not have stable, logically rigorous notions of free will,” the researchers found. After conducting a series of studies probing people’s philosophical intuitions, the researchers concluded that people seem to be flexible in their views. They don’t have “one intuition about whether free will is compatible with determinism,” the researchers concluded. “Instead, people report that free will is compatible with determinism when desiring to uphold moral responsibility.”
The concept of free will doesn’t make any sense to me. As Kavka’s thought experiment shows, we don’t have much control over our thoughts. Take this article I’m writing: The words I’m committing to print pop into my mind unbeckoned. It’s less me choosing them and more them presenting themselves to me. The act of writing feels more like a process of passive filtration than active conjuration. I’m also convinced that humans can sensibly hold one another morally responsible even if we jettison the idea of free will. The reason is that, as a social mechanism, it has salutary effects. Generally, if people know that they will be held to account for moral violations, they will be less likely to commit them; and if they don’t know what the moral rules are, they will be motivated to learn them. Indeed, in the study on compatibilism, the researchers found that “participants reduced their compatibilist beliefs after reading a passage that argued that moral responsibility could be preserved even in the absence of free will.”
In any case, the mystery of free will isn’t going away anytime soon. In March, a group of neuroscientists and philosophers announced that they’ve received $7 million to study the nature of free will and whether humans have it. Uri Maoz, a computational neuroscientist at Chapman University, is leading the project. “As a scientist, I don’t know what it entails to have free will,” he said in an interview with Science. That’s a philosophical puzzle. But once Maoz’s philosopher colleagues agree on a definition, he can get to work to see if it occurs in humans. “This is an empirical question. It may be that I don’t have the technology to measure it, but that is at least an empirical question that I could get at.”
Maybe, as Chidi said looking at his M.R.I. results, there will be answers there, data we can observe and learn from. Perhaps free will won’t forever be an issue philosophers mull over for a lifetime. Whatever the result, there’s always the ironic answer to the question of whether we have free will: “Of course we do. We have no choice.”
In The Good Place, a cerebral fantasy-comedy TV series, moral philosophy gets teased. On YouTube, the show released a promotional video, “This Is Why Everyone Hates Moral Philosophy,” that gets its title from a line directed at Chidi, a Senegalese professor of moral philosophy who suffers from chronic indecision: The pros and cons of even trivial choices have long paralyzed him. We see him, as a precocious boy, urged to get on with picking teammates for a soccer game. Flustered, Chidi explains, “I have to consider all the factors: athletic strategies, the fragile egos of my classmates, and gender politics! Should I pick a girl as a gesture toward women’s equality, or is that pandering? Or do I think it’s pandering because of my limited male point of view? I’m vexed!” The kids waiting to play shake their heads, facepalming. A friend later insists he “fix his brain.” An M.R.I., courtesy of a neuroscientist named Simone, shows he’s fine. “Wow, there are actual answers here—data you can observe, and learn from,” Chidi says. “Yeah, man! Science is all about getting answers,” Simone replies. “You philosophers can spend your entire life mulling over a single question. That’s why everyone hates moral philosophy professors.” Both of them chuckle and she adds, “No offense.”
This is mock-hate, born of love. Before Mike Schur, the show’s creator, started shooting scenes, he paid a visit to the UCLA moral philosopher Pamela Hieronymi for insight. She’s interested in the sort of control humans have over our intentions and emotions, and how it might differ from control over our actions. Her favorite thought experiment comes from a 1983 paper, “The Toxin Puzzle,” by Gregory Kavka. A delightful head-scratcher, it invites you to imagine that an eccentric billionaire has offered you a deal: If you merely intend to drink a toxin tonight, at midnight, that will make you painfully ill for a day, he will wire you a million dollars—it’ll be in your bank tomorrow morning. A sophisticated and reliable brain scanner will determine whether you really formed the intention to imbibe the toxin. After you have the funds in your bank account, you’re free to decide not to drink it. An easy way to become a millionaire, no? Just intend to drink it for the scanner and, once you have the cash, switch your intention.
The sense of freedom we have to act on our moral understanding is regulated and vulnerable, and can break.
This is absurd, of course, and that’s Kavka’s point: We don’t have that sort of control over ourselves. If you intend to drink it (for the sake of the scanner) but also intend, later, to not drink it (to avoid the sickness), you’re really intending to not drink it. Our intentions are only “partly volitional,” Kavka says. “One cannot intend whatever one wants to intend any more than one can believe whatever one wants to believe. As our beliefs are constrained by our evidence, so our intentions are constrained by our reasons for action.” The sense that you have of being in control, of having free will, is just that—a sense. And it can break.
Clinical neuroscientists and neurologists have identified the brain networks responsible for this sense of free will. There seems to be two: the network governing the desire to act, and the network governing the feeling of responsibility for acting. Brain-damaged patients show that these can come apart—you can have one without the other.
Lacking essentially all motivation to move or speak has a name: akinetic mutism. The researchers, lead by neurologists Michael Fox, of Harvard Medical School, and Ryan Darby, of Vanderbilt University, analyzed 28 cases of this condition, not all of them involving damage in the same departments. “We found that brain lesions that disrupt volition occur in many different locations, but fall within a single brain network, defined by connectivity to the anterior cingulate,” which has links to both the “emotional” limbic system and the “cognitive” prefrontal cortex, the researchers wrote. Feeling like you’re moving under the direction of outside forces has a name, too: alien limb syndrome. The researchers analyzed 50 cases of this condition, which again involved brain damage in different spots. “Lesions that disrupt agency also occur in many different locations, but fall within a separate network, defined by connectivity to the precuneus,” which is involved, among other things, in the experience of agency.
The results may not map onto “free will” as we understand it ethically—the ability to choose between right and wrong. “It remains unknown whether the network of brain regions we identify as related to free will for movements is the same as those important for moral decision-making, as prior studies have suggested important differences,” the researchers wrote. For instance, in a 2017 study, he and Darby analyzed many cases of brain lesions in various regions predisposing people to criminal behavior, and found that “these lesions all fall within a unique functionally connected brain network involved in moral decision making.”
Nevertheless, the fact that brain damage affects moral behavior only underscores the reality that, whatever the “will” is, it isn’t “free.” The sense of freedom we have to act on our moral understanding is regulated and vulnerable, and can break. In a 2016 paper, Darby noted that people who have behavioral-variant frontotemporal dementia “develop immoral behaviors as a result of their disease despite the ability to explicitly state that their behavior is wrong.” This complicates how moral responsibility should be understood, he explains. People can be capable of acknowledging wrongdoing and yet be incapable of acting accordingly. Responsibility can’t hinge on any simple notion of “reason responsiveness,” Darby says, which is a view of how free will can be compatible with determinism—the idea, in the case of behavior, that brain activity causes feelings, intentions, and actions, moral or not.
It’s still not clear whether lay people tend to lean toward “compatibilism” or not. Experimental philosophers have been trying to find out for years, but haven’t landed on a consensus. A recent study explains why: “People are strongly motivated to preserve free will and moral responsibility, and thus do not have stable, logically rigorous notions of free will,” the researchers found. After conducting a series of studies probing people’s philosophical intuitions, the researchers concluded that people seem to be flexible in their views. They don’t have “one intuition about whether free will is compatible with determinism,” the researchers concluded. “Instead, people report that free will is compatible with determinism when desiring to uphold moral responsibility.”
The concept of free will doesn’t make any sense to me. As Kavka’s thought experiment shows, we don’t have much control over our thoughts. Take this article I’m writing: The words I’m committing to print pop into my mind unbeckoned. It’s less me choosing them and more them presenting themselves to me. The act of writing feels more like a process of passive filtration than active conjuration. I’m also convinced that humans can sensibly hold one another morally responsible even if we jettison the idea of free will. The reason is that, as a social mechanism, it has salutary effects. Generally, if people know that they will be held to account for moral violations, they will be less likely to commit them; and if they don’t know what the moral rules are, they will be motivated to learn them. Indeed, in the study on compatibilism, the researchers found that “participants reduced their compatibilist beliefs after reading a passage that argued that moral responsibility could be preserved even in the absence of free will.”
In any case, the mystery of free will isn’t going away anytime soon. In March, a group of neuroscientists and philosophers announced that they’ve received $7 million to study the nature of free will and whether humans have it. Uri Maoz, a computational neuroscientist at Chapman University, is leading the project. “As a scientist, I don’t know what it entails to have free will,” he said in an interview with Science. That’s a philosophical puzzle. But once Maoz’s philosopher colleagues agree on a definition, he can get to work to see if it occurs in humans. “This is an empirical question. It may be that I don’t have the technology to measure it, but that is at least an empirical question that I could get at.”
Maybe, as Chidi said looking at his M.R.I. results, there will be answers there, data we can observe and learn from. Perhaps free will won’t forever be an issue philosophers mull over for a lifetime. Whatever the result, there’s always the ironic answer to the question of whether we have free will: “Of course we do. We have no choice.”
Monday, August 12, 2019
Is life a dream?
via Psychology Today
One of the strange things about dreams is that, most of the time, we aren’t aware we’re dreaming. Typically, our memory and our reflective ability are substantially limited within dreams (Fosse et al. 2003; Hobson et al. 1998), causing us not to notice incongruencies within the dream and to take for granted that what we experience is real. It simply doesn’t occur to us to consider whether it might not be.
Perhaps even more strangely, even when we do on occasion become aware that we’re dreaming—and according to various surveys carried out around the world, anywhere from 26% to 92% of people have had at least one lucid dream (Stepansky et al. 1998; Erlacher et al. 2008; Palmer 1979; Yu 2008)—the “sensory” experiences of the dream can remain just as convincingly real. I remember in one of my own dreams realizing that it was a dream and then marveling at how solid and real the cell phone in my hand still felt.
The ability of the dream world to appear real has led many thinkers—philosopher RenĂ© Descartes (1641) being the most prominent Western example—to wonder whether the world we experience while awake might itself be a dream. If the dream world feels just as real as the waking one (at least while we are in it), how can we know for sure that we’re not currently living in a dream—a dream from which we may one day wake up?
One way that philosophers have tried to dispel such worries is by appealing to differences between the dream world and the waking one. For instance, our waking world has a coherence that the dream world often lacks. (For an example of a coherence-based argument against the skeptical hypothesis, see Norman Malcolm (1959).) You may recall that, in the feature film Inception, the characters learn to recognize that they’re dreaming by asking themselves how they came to be in a certain situation, then realizing that they can’t remember, because the dream just dropped them there.
But does the coherence of our waking world guarantee that it’s real?
I believe the coherence of our waking world does give us evidence that it is not merely a figment of our imagination. Specifically, it gives us evidence that, when we are awake, something is causing our experience that is independent of the experience itself. For instance, the relative permanence of the objects and environments we experience in waking life would appear to be best explained by there being something real and enduring that our experiences are reflecting.
However, the relative permanence of the objects and environments we encounter in the waking world is no guarantee that the waking world is as real as it gets. After all, a high degree of permanence is also found in the worlds of video games, in which the “environments” and “objects” one interacts with are merely the creations of computer code. So, while perceived permanence does seem to point to there being something objective/enduring out there, the true nature of whatever is “out there” might resemble our experience of it as little as computer code resembles the images we see when we play a video game.
In fact, physics teaches us that the objects we experience as being solid are actually made up almost entirely of empty space. And the results of quantum mechanical experiments indicate that, under certain conditions, the building blocks of matter do not behave as discrete particles at all, but rather as waves of probability. If we nevertheless experience the world as full of enduring, solid objects, this is due to the usual way that our senses interact with it and to the way these interactions are represented in consciousness.
This means that there is, in fact, an important sense in which all of us do live constantly within a dream—that is, within a world created by our own minds. It’s just that, when we’re awake, our minds conform our dreaming to a reliable set of patterns, which we assume to be determined by a reality that exists independently of our experience of it, though we have no way of knowing that reality except through the complex ways in which it affects our “dream.”
But might there be an even deeper sense in which our waking life is a dream?
Just as we often wake from sleep to realize that what we were experiencing in the sleep state was not nearly as coherent and “real” as what we experience when awake, could there possibly come a day when we will emerge from the dream of waking reality to experience a world that is even more coherent and vividly real, a state in which we experience levels of knowledge, memory, and other cognitive function that vastly surpass those we experience in our current lives?
In fact, a rather startling number of people report having already had experiences like this. That is, they report having had experiences that appear to them as even more real than those they have in their normal, waking state of mind. For example, “realer than real” is a description often used by those who have had near-death experiences (Moody 1975; Thonnard et al. 2013; Palmieri et al. 2014), those who have used psychedelic drugs such as DMT (Strassman 2001), and those who, by various other means, have experienced non-ordinary states of consciousness.
Many near-death experiencers also report enhanced cognitive function and a sudden increase in knowledge (Owens et al. 1990; Greyson 2003). This perception of enhanced cognitive function and increased knowledge is often dismissed as an illusion by those who are unfamiliar with the scientific literature on near-death experiences, but careful investigation has shown that concrete, verifiable information has been obtained in these states that was not available to the experiencer by way of their five senses (Rivas et al. 2016).
The experience of those who have tasted non-ordinary states of consciousness raises the possibility that the age-old question of whether “life is but a dream” is more than the idle worry of a few philosophers comfortably ensconced in their armchairs by the fire. The answer to this question could very well have major empirical consequences, including startling implications for the types of experiences that are available to the human mind. We have every reason to stay alert to this possibility as we continue to investigate the true nature of the world that we take ourselves to be living in.
References
Descartes, R. (1641). Meditations on First Philosophy.
Erlacher, D., Schredl, M., Watanabe, T., Yamana, J., and Gantzert, F. (2008). The incidence of lucid dreaming within a Japanese university student sample. International Journal of Dream Research 1(2): 39–43.
Fosse, M. J., Fosse, R., Hobson, J. A., and Stickgold, R. J. (2003). Dreaming and episodic memory: a functional dissociation? Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience 15(1): 1–9.
One of the strange things about dreams is that, most of the time, we aren’t aware we’re dreaming. Typically, our memory and our reflective ability are substantially limited within dreams (Fosse et al. 2003; Hobson et al. 1998), causing us not to notice incongruencies within the dream and to take for granted that what we experience is real. It simply doesn’t occur to us to consider whether it might not be.
Perhaps even more strangely, even when we do on occasion become aware that we’re dreaming—and according to various surveys carried out around the world, anywhere from 26% to 92% of people have had at least one lucid dream (Stepansky et al. 1998; Erlacher et al. 2008; Palmer 1979; Yu 2008)—the “sensory” experiences of the dream can remain just as convincingly real. I remember in one of my own dreams realizing that it was a dream and then marveling at how solid and real the cell phone in my hand still felt.
The ability of the dream world to appear real has led many thinkers—philosopher RenĂ© Descartes (1641) being the most prominent Western example—to wonder whether the world we experience while awake might itself be a dream. If the dream world feels just as real as the waking one (at least while we are in it), how can we know for sure that we’re not currently living in a dream—a dream from which we may one day wake up?
One way that philosophers have tried to dispel such worries is by appealing to differences between the dream world and the waking one. For instance, our waking world has a coherence that the dream world often lacks. (For an example of a coherence-based argument against the skeptical hypothesis, see Norman Malcolm (1959).) You may recall that, in the feature film Inception, the characters learn to recognize that they’re dreaming by asking themselves how they came to be in a certain situation, then realizing that they can’t remember, because the dream just dropped them there.
But does the coherence of our waking world guarantee that it’s real?
I believe the coherence of our waking world does give us evidence that it is not merely a figment of our imagination. Specifically, it gives us evidence that, when we are awake, something is causing our experience that is independent of the experience itself. For instance, the relative permanence of the objects and environments we experience in waking life would appear to be best explained by there being something real and enduring that our experiences are reflecting.
However, the relative permanence of the objects and environments we encounter in the waking world is no guarantee that the waking world is as real as it gets. After all, a high degree of permanence is also found in the worlds of video games, in which the “environments” and “objects” one interacts with are merely the creations of computer code. So, while perceived permanence does seem to point to there being something objective/enduring out there, the true nature of whatever is “out there” might resemble our experience of it as little as computer code resembles the images we see when we play a video game.
In fact, physics teaches us that the objects we experience as being solid are actually made up almost entirely of empty space. And the results of quantum mechanical experiments indicate that, under certain conditions, the building blocks of matter do not behave as discrete particles at all, but rather as waves of probability. If we nevertheless experience the world as full of enduring, solid objects, this is due to the usual way that our senses interact with it and to the way these interactions are represented in consciousness.
This means that there is, in fact, an important sense in which all of us do live constantly within a dream—that is, within a world created by our own minds. It’s just that, when we’re awake, our minds conform our dreaming to a reliable set of patterns, which we assume to be determined by a reality that exists independently of our experience of it, though we have no way of knowing that reality except through the complex ways in which it affects our “dream.”
But might there be an even deeper sense in which our waking life is a dream?
Just as we often wake from sleep to realize that what we were experiencing in the sleep state was not nearly as coherent and “real” as what we experience when awake, could there possibly come a day when we will emerge from the dream of waking reality to experience a world that is even more coherent and vividly real, a state in which we experience levels of knowledge, memory, and other cognitive function that vastly surpass those we experience in our current lives?
In fact, a rather startling number of people report having already had experiences like this. That is, they report having had experiences that appear to them as even more real than those they have in their normal, waking state of mind. For example, “realer than real” is a description often used by those who have had near-death experiences (Moody 1975; Thonnard et al. 2013; Palmieri et al. 2014), those who have used psychedelic drugs such as DMT (Strassman 2001), and those who, by various other means, have experienced non-ordinary states of consciousness.
Many near-death experiencers also report enhanced cognitive function and a sudden increase in knowledge (Owens et al. 1990; Greyson 2003). This perception of enhanced cognitive function and increased knowledge is often dismissed as an illusion by those who are unfamiliar with the scientific literature on near-death experiences, but careful investigation has shown that concrete, verifiable information has been obtained in these states that was not available to the experiencer by way of their five senses (Rivas et al. 2016).
The experience of those who have tasted non-ordinary states of consciousness raises the possibility that the age-old question of whether “life is but a dream” is more than the idle worry of a few philosophers comfortably ensconced in their armchairs by the fire. The answer to this question could very well have major empirical consequences, including startling implications for the types of experiences that are available to the human mind. We have every reason to stay alert to this possibility as we continue to investigate the true nature of the world that we take ourselves to be living in.
References
Descartes, R. (1641). Meditations on First Philosophy.
Erlacher, D., Schredl, M., Watanabe, T., Yamana, J., and Gantzert, F. (2008). The incidence of lucid dreaming within a Japanese university student sample. International Journal of Dream Research 1(2): 39–43.
Fosse, M. J., Fosse, R., Hobson, J. A., and Stickgold, R. J. (2003). Dreaming and episodic memory: a functional dissociation? Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience 15(1): 1–9.
Labels:
descartes,
dream,
life,
near-death experience,
waking life
Sunday, August 11, 2019
Remembering Sandy Hook
I
will begin this article by stating forthrightly that I am a “conspiracy
theorist” in the normative sense of the term. That is, I am someone who
supposes that conspiratorial activity takes place between people of
means and power in a way that is not a matter of public record. I
contend that this is the default position of sanity and I assert that
those who have a particular problem with the assertion I just made are
what might be colloquially called “idiots”.
Taking
my cue from 9/11 and the egregious violations of common sense that
attended that event, I have come to see the “fourth estate” in North
America as non-existent. In its place is, I contend, a sophisticated
propaganda apparatus that supports the varied agendas of our plutocratic
rulers, whose vested interest in endless war is furthered via the
manifactured consent of the masses through strict narrative control.
I
contend that most of the civilian mass shootings and killings in recent
history in the Western democracies have been the result of a social
engineering program(s) by various intelligence agencies in support of
specific agendas. I have suspected this for a while. What really caught
my attention was Sandy Hook, and it is that event which I wish to
examine in detail in the remainder of this article. I realize it is past
history, but in recent days there has been a disturbing sign that soon
“conspiracy theorists” are going to be labeled as domestic terrorists
just for entertaining such thoughts, so I thought I would lay out the
case for Sandy Hook being fishy while it is still legal to do so.
Let
me begin, then, by emphasizing that I don’t know what transpired at
Sandy Hook. I wasn’t there, I wasn’t involved. What I do know is that
the “official” narrative surrounding Sandy Hook as presented by various
media sources was flawed and questionable. I am willing to have my mind
changed about this, but to change my mind, someone would have to address
the following points to my satisfaction. Much of the following text was
borrowed from an article written by James Tracey which I can no longer
find online.
1.> Details omitted. The New York Times,
the “official historians” of the United States, concluded its final
report on Sandy Hook with an article that did not include the names,
ages, or gender of the alleged victims of the shooting. The only time in
the history of crime reporting that such information has been omitted
has been in the case of sex crimes.
2.>
Twenty-eight people allegedly died: 27 children and adults, including
Adam Lanza, at the school, and his mother, Nancy Lanza, in her home at
36 Yogananda Street, Newtown. However, there is no direct proof of their
death: no photographic evidence or video footage was released to
confirm the official story that these 28 persons actually died. In fact,
no video surveillance footage shows anything — not even Adam shooting
out the front plate-glass window or walking through the halls like
Rambo, even though this is a school that had updated its security system
at the start of the 2012–13 academic year.
Compounding
the situation, the parents were not even allowed to view their
children’s bodies to identify them. Instead, they were reportedly shown
photographs of the deceased. This was done, according to the Medical
Examiner, Wayne Carver, in order to “control the situation.” But what
was there about the situation that required “control”? No parent of our
acquaintance would have agreed to accept the death of a child without
viewing the body. James Tracy has published a discussion of the medical examiner’s performance. According to Carver:
Uh, we did not bring the bodies and the families into contact. We took pictures of them, uhm, of their facial features. We have, uh, uh — it’s easier on the families when you do that. Un, there is, uh, a time and place for the up close and personal in the grieving process, but to accomplish this we thought it would be best to do it this way and, uh, you can sort of, uh … You can control a situation depending on the photographer, and I have very good photographers. Uh, but uh —
Remarkably,
the state has done its best to avoid releasing the death certificates
and even recordings of the 911 calls. Death certificates were eventually
“released” but not to the public or those who might want to investigate
the case further, where only a short, general summary was available.
According to The New York Times,
in relation to the 911 calls, “no children are identified by name, no
callers indicate that they can see a child being shot, and the only
injury described is that of an educator’s being shot in the foot.”
Moreover,
the funerals were all “closed casket,” with one exception — that of
Noah Pozner, which supposedly included a private viewing before the
public ceremony.. As recounted in interviews with the families, the
circumstances of their last encounters with their children (or with
their caskets) are strange to say the least.
3.>
There is no evidence of any frantic effort to save lives or to remove
bodies to hospitals; instead the scene outside the school looked calm
and largely bloodless — with police and other personnel milling around
casually and a severe shortage of dead or injured victims.
In
a Mass Casualty Incident (MCI) like Sandy Hook, the proper protocol is
START triage (Simple Triage and Rapid Treatment) using tarps of
different colors with the aim being to save lives and get the injured to
the hospital for treatment. Not even the black tarps for the dead were
used, much less the red ones for those who needed immediate treatment.
Sandy
Hook Fire Chief Bill Halstead was ready to help the victims but could
recall only two wounded people. A few survivors were reportedly taken to
the hospital, but, oddly, these people were never interviewed. There
were no first-hand accounts that proved anyone was killed or injured.
Nonetheless, according to Lt. Vance, 18 children were pronounced dead at
the scene, two children were removed to “an area hospital” and were
pronounced dead at the hospital, and seven adults were pronounced dead
at the scene, including the shooter (NBC).
No
emergency vehicles were present at the school or even lined up in the
fire lane for a rescue attempt — the parking lot was filled with parked
cars, police cars and possibly media vehicles. Such rescue activity as
occurred was centered, not on the school premises, but at the nearby
Firehouse. Emergency vehicles at the Firehouse were jammed together
impeding access to the school, in case anyone might have thought about
attempting a rescue. The scene at the Firehouse was quite peculiar, with
people milling around and circling through the building, walking out
one door and into another.
4.>
According to initial reports in the media, weapons used in the shooting
included four handguns recovered at the scene, the only guns taken into
the school (NBC). Then an AR-15 was said to have been found in the
trunk of Lanza’s car (NBC). Then it was reported that Lanza may have
carried only two handguns and that a rifle was also found in the school
(NBC).
Wayne
Carver, the Medical Examiner, said that all the victims were shot with
the “long weapon.” Lt. Paul Vance then said that a Bushmaster AR-15
assault weapon with high capacity magazines was used “most of the time”
and that Lanza was carrying “many high-capacity clips” for the weapon
(Huffington Post).
In
January 2013, Connecticut state police released a statement indicating
that they had found four guns inside the school: a Bushmaster .223
caliber XM 15-E2S semi-automatic rifle with high capacity 30 round
clips, a Glock 10-mm handgun and a Sig-Sauer P226 9mm handgun. They said
they also found an Izhmash Canta-12 12-gauge shotgun in Lanza’s car
(NBC).
Lt. Vance then asserted that Lanza had killed all his victims with the .223-caliber semi-automatic rifle (ctpost.com).
Regarding the confusion, Vance told reporters, “It’s all these
conspiracy theorists that are trying to mucky up the waters.” Perhaps
“The Top Prize for Fantastical Reporting” goes to Fox News, however,
which announced that a 12-gauge shotgun along with two magazines
containing 70 rounds of Winchester 12-gauge shotgun rounds had been
found in the glove compartment of Adam Lanza’s Honda Civic — that’s right, in the glove compartment.
5.>
Adam Lanza can’t have carried out the shooting. Adam Lanza, reportedly a
frail young man weighing 120 pounds with Asperger’s Syndrome, is said
to have carried massive weaponry on his person when he shot his way into
the Sandy Hook school and proceeded to kill 26 people and then himself.
This after he supposedly killed his mother before driving to the
school.
According
to State’s Attorney Stephen Sedensky, Lanza killed his 26 victims with
the Bushmaster .223-caliber rifle and then killed himself with his Glock
10-mm handgun. Lanza was also supposedly carrying three 30-round
magazines for the Bushmaster as well as a Sig-Sauer 9 mm handgun (see
above). The victims were shot multiple times each in a fusillade of
bullets from these military-style weapons. In order to wreak this havoc,
he fired more than 150 rounds, and he must have carried more rounds in
addition. Lanza was reportedly found dead wearing a bulletproof vest and
military-style clothing (AP).
As
Mike Powers, a professional military investigator and ballistics
expert, has observed, this young man of slight build could not have
carried all these heavy, bulky weapons and ammunition on his person.
Furthermore, since first responders were supposedly inside the school
within seven minutes, there was not enough time for Lanza to have
carried out the shooting as reported. In an interview with Joyce Riley,
Powers states that Lanza could not have fired so many times continuously
without destabilizing himself from the intense noise from the
Bushmaster. As a novice, he could not have shot an AR-15 with such speed
and accuracy, supposedly changing magazines 8–10 times without a
stoppage.
According
to Lt. Vance on the night of the shooting, one victim survived. So in
less than seven minutes — or less than five minutes according to the
media — Lanza killed 26 people and then himself, producing only one
injured victim. This is a 96% kill ratio, which is unheard-of accuracy
among the most experienced marksmen. Powers thinks the whole scenario is
a physical impossibility. He is not even convinced that Adam Lanza was a
real person. The story of the shooting should not be taken seriously.
The final travesty involves the weapons and other paraphernalia that were allegedly found in the Lanza house.
The “arsenal” supposedly included guns, Samurai swords, knives, a
bayonet and more than 1,000 rounds of ammunition, according to search
warrants released. Other items of interest were ear and eye protection,
binoculars, holsters, manuals, paper targets, a military-style uniform
and Lanza’s NRA certificate (Fox). Lanza had reportedly compiled a
spreadsheet 7 feet long and 4 feet wide in 9-point type detailing 500
victims of other mass murders (CBS). We are supposed to believe this,
and, at the same time, that Adam Lanza was a shy, quiet kid who didn’t
like noise and chaos, as promoted by the PBS Frontline Special,“Raising Adam Lanza.”
6.>
A man dressed in black was seen fleeing into the woods from the site of
the incident. Police chased him, apprehended him, and put him in
handcuffs in the back of their squad car. Video of this is readily
available on Youtube for the time being. Seem plausible to you that none
of the news networks had any interest in covering this angle of the
story?
7.>
Key participants displayed bizarre behaviour. There are many bizarre
media reports and interviews of those associated with the “shooting.”
Some examples:
Wayne Carver — Medical
Examiner Wayne Carver’s surreal press conference is one of the most
startling of all the media offerings. Widely available on youtube, this
event shows H. Wayne Carver II, a public official of some standing,
clowning and acting outlandish — grinning strangely, making irrelevant
comments, and basically appearing unknowledgeable and unprofessional.
Robbie Parker — Perhaps
the most famous press conference is that of Robbie Parker, the alleged
father of victim Emilie Parker, speaking on a CNN report of December 15,
2012. He chuckles as he walks up to the camera, then gets into
character by hyperventilating, and finally feigns distress as he talks
about his daughter — and about the fund set up to help raise money “for
Emilie.”
The families — In
addition to Robbie and Alissa Parker, other parents and family members
take their turn in the spotlight, including (but not limited to) Mark
and Jackie Barden, Jimmy Greene and Nelba Marquez-Greene, Ian and Nicole
Hockley, Neil Heslin (alleged father of Jesse Lewis), Chris and Lynn
McDonnell, Veronique Pozner, Carlee Soto, and David and Francine
Wheeler. Anderson Cooper is the interviewer in two notable instances:
his conversation with the McDonnells mentioned above, and an interview
with Veronique Pozner, remarkable for its green-screen effects such as
Anderson’s disappearing nose.
The school nurse — Numerous
reports offer detailed and totally fictitious information, some of
which was later abandoned in favor of more tenable versions. On the
evening of December 14, a USA Today reporter said she had spoken with
the school nurse, whom she had met on the street. The nurse told her
that the gunman had come into her office, “they met eyes, she jumped
under her desk,” and he walked out. The nurse said that the gunman was
the son of the kindergarten teacher, who was known to her and “an
absolutely loving person.” It later developed that Nancy Lanza had not
been a kindergarten teacher at all, and that neither Nancy nor Adam had
any connection to Sandy Hook school whatsoever.
Dawn Hochsprung — In an embarrassing fiction, The Newtown Bee
reported on 14 December 2013 that Dawn Hochsprung, the Sandy Hook
school principal, told the paper that a masked man had entered the
school with a rifle and started shooting multiple shots — more than she
could count — that went “on and on.” Of course, Dawn Hochsprung was
allegedly killed by Adam Lanza and so could not easily have provided
this statement. In fact, Dawn was said to have acted heroically, dying
while lunging at the gunman — although one wonders who witnessed and
reported this act of heroism. On 17 December 2013, The Bee retracted the report and apologized:
An early online report from the scene at the December 14 shootings at Sandy Hook Elementary School quoted a woman who identified herself to our reporter as the principal of the school. The woman was not the school’s principal, Dawn Hochsprung, who was killed in the Friday morning attack. The quote was removed from subsequent online versions of the story, but the original story did remain in our online archive for three days before being deleted. We apologize for whatever confusion this may have caused our readers and for any pain or anguish it may have caused the Hochsprung family.
Now,
let’s be clear. None of this is proof that “nobody died at Sandy Hook”
or that “crisis actors” were involved in creating a dramatic spectacle. I
am not a fan of trying to figure out what did actually happen in these
cases, because theories can be tenuous and become low-hanging fruit for
people to debunk or make straw men out of. All I know is what didn’t
happen at Sandy Hook, and I know Adam Lanza didn’t single-handedly
murder multiple children in the way we were led to believe. The evidence
to say otherwise doesn’t exist.
I’m
not sure any of this will matter to those who are determined to ignore
it because of cognitive dissonance or whatever, but I thought it was
worth the effort to preserve some of this information for those who in
the coming days need to know the history of what appears to be an
ongoing effort to engineer consent for an enhanced police state.
Two
things stick in my mind about the Sandy Hook ordeal more than anything
else. One was the photo of Adam Lanza that was circulated… his eyes
vacant, his face expressionless, his cheeks hollow and sunken… due to a
very very obvious photoshopping of his likeness. The other thing that
sticks in my mind was Barack Obama breaking down in tears while
discussing the event, and again four years later… a career politician, a
hard-nosed pragmatist, bomber of 8 countries, surely no stranger to
political theatre. One might well imagine his teleprompter at the time
read: “weep here”. I don’t know much, but I know when someone is trying
to manipulate my feelings and jerk me around. I’ve worked in sales
enough to be that cynical.
I can only conclude that we’ve been conditioned to be duped and that
we’re being not-so-subtly played by people even more cynical than I am.
Perhaps it takes a cynic to see the handiwork of others, I donno.
Anyways, from the looks of things, the other shoe is about to drop.
Perhaps it’s best that it does… it seems like those who aren’t already
awake to this kind of thing have made a choice to stay asleep. I’m not
sure it’s my place to tell them that’s a bad idea.
Labels:
adam lanza,
conspiracy theory,
false flag,
psyop,
sandy hook,
wayne carver
Friday, August 9, 2019
Changing your mind about "Pizzagate"
I
have been wondering for quite some time now about whether to try
writing about this topic, how I would approach it, and what the
repercussions might be for making the attempt. In recent days, having
had some time to reflect on the topic and take some renewed interest in
it, I guess I have decided that the best thing to do is just go for it,
even though I am not gleefully anticipating the blowback I imagine I’ll
take from friends and acquaintances.
The
difficulty I’m having here is, I want to change your mind about
something, but I don’t really think I can. As you might have noticed
from your own forays into using the internet, changing people’s minds
about things is notoriously difficult… and that sad situation is only
getting worse. There are reasons for this… some of them have to do with
basic human psychology, some of them have to do with the increasing
deadening of our critical faculties by bombardment from questionable
information sources, some of them have to do with our own intellectual
laziness and willingness to go along with propaganda.
Of
course, it has been noted that ‘literacy’ in the 21st century will be a
word used to describe those whose opinions can remain fluid enough to
change with new information. But that can and must be a gradual process.
Drastic changes of opinion in a short period of time are extremely
disorienting.
So
with that out of the way, what I’d like to do is pitch a really absurd,
far-out, wild-sounding idea that you’ve probably already encountered,
and been so offended or short-circuited by that your brain just
immediately went ‘nope, not having that’ and switched itself off,
allowing you to get on with your life. It’s a shocking idea, a
horrendous idea, a heartbreaking idea, and at first glance, a seemingly
absurd idea so alien and repulsive that it feels ethically wrong to even
contemplate it. And I don’t want you to believe me, or take me at my
word. I’m asking you to empathize with me when I tell you the story of
how and why I changed my mind.
You
see, I am an average middle-aged Joe from Canada. Never married, no
kids. I struggle with my weight and my mental health. I like science
fiction and I like playing board games with my buddies and I like
take-out food. I have been diagnosed with schizo affective disorder, and
anyone who cares to do away with my opinions on that basis can
doubtlessly do so easily. I’ve had a lot of trouble coming to terms with
what I know and with what I think I can prove. It’s hard to keep a
sunny perspective about the human species or its prospects sometimes.
You see, I have come to be of the opinion that our civilization appears
to be run, at the highest level from behind the scenes, by literal
Satan-worshipping child molestors. And I sometimes wonder how to live in
a world like that.
Yes,
I know. Many of you think this is alt-right troll chatter from the
bowels of neckbeard 4chan, and I’ve lost my mind, and there’s all sorts
of reasons why it just can’t be so. I hear you. I mean, what can I say? I
could start by saying I skew politically left-libertarian in terms of
my ideology. I think it’s important to falsify the notion that this is a
‘right wing’ talking point. I could then point to examples of UK
pop culture icons who were high-ranking Freemasons and friends of the
Royal family who are documented to have worn robes, chanted Satanic
prayers, and raped children, but what you want is proof. You want to
hiss at me that I’m a kooky conspiracy theorist. You want to get on
with your life and pretend this is just nonsense.
Well,
I mean, I wish you were right. I really do. And man, I really feel for
you, because there’s nothing I’d rather be doing right now than smoking a
joint and playing a video game and saving the world from imagined alien
menaces. I mean, I don’t have kids, so I have no actual personal
investment in what kind of world this turns out to be in the long run,
it might be argued. I guess I’m thinking about those of you who do have
something to live for though. I mean, hypothetically, I guess, I have to
say that I find myself wondering, if this kind of, well, let’s call it
‘evil’, is actually, factually, loose in the world, doesn’t our refusal
to acknowledge it kind of, like, make us complicit?
I
think pondering questions like the one I just posed will give you some
indication of why so-called ‘conspiracy theorists’ are so invested in
their hobby of trying to get people to think outside of their current
abstractions.
Let’s
talk, briefly, about that ‘conspiracy theorist’ thing. If you find the
words ‘conspiracy theory’ coming to mind as you read this, you kind of
need to be honest with yourself that that’s a knee-jerk reaction. Ask
yourself this; are you using the term in the pejorative or normative
sense? If it’s the pejorative, then please admit to yourself that it’s
intellectually dishonest by definition to construct a criticism of
another’s position that is founded on pejorative epithets. If you are
using the term in the normative sense, intending to allege only that I
am supposing that human beings occasionally can be observed to collude
in their own best interests in ways which aren’t a matter of public
record, then I am in agreement with you. You and I are both conspiracy
theorists in the normative sense, and well we should be, for that is the
default position of sanity. So now we are just arguing about how far
along things have gone downhill.
My
perspective on such things shifted gradually over the course of many
years, having taken a steep turn into less-familiar territory around the
time of 9/11 in 2001. I had always thought of governments as stupid and
myopic, but I was initially slow to embrace the idea that the powers
that be could be deliberately malevolent. I think many of us hide from
facing the idea that things aren’t all on the up-and-up because it
becomes an exercise in recognizing evil in oneself. But, for example, if
we contemplate war and its nature for very long, it becomes fairly
obvious that the people who profit from such activity are deeply
unhealthy and malevolent. The question then becomes not “How could
anybody think the world works this way?”, but rather, “How could anybody
think otherwise?”
“Pizzagate”
was a term given to a putatively debunked ‘conspiracy theory’ that a
child molestation ring was being run out of a Washington, D.C. Pizza
parlour. If you look it up on Wikipedia, you will find a detailed
outline of the ‘facts’ surrounding this bizarre controversy and you will
be soundly assured in no-nonsense language that it has all been
thoroughly discredited by everyone, not least of which by that stalwart
defender of reason and right-thinking snopes.com
I don’t believe it has been ‘debunked’ at all, and I am presenting forthwith the facts that changed my mind on the topic.
1.>
Wikileaks published John Podesta’s emails. Some allege these
publications were falsified. People who say so are ignoring the fact
that John Podesta has admitted via Twitter that the emails are in fact
his.
2.>
The emails contain multiple examples of Podesta and his allies emailing
each other strange gibberish involving what appear to be food-related
codewords. Stuff like “Do you think I’ll do better playing dominos on
cheese than on pasta?” Some folks think these code words relate to some
clandestine activity, and some specifically allege they relate to
pedophilia. One letter indicates Obama, for one function, spent 65,000
dollars of public funds to fly “hot dogs” in from Chicago.
3.>
James Alefantis, a friend of Podesta’s, is mentioned multiple times in
those emails. Alefantis runs an ostensibly family-friendly pizza joint
in Washington named Comet Ping Pong.
He is well-connected politically, considered (by GQ Magazine at least) a
Washington power player for some reason, and is the former partner of
David Brock (described by Time as “one of the most influential
operatives in the Democratic party”) who runs the Democratic “media
watchdog group” Media Matters.
4.> People visiting Alefantis’ public profile in Instagram for his restaurant found a great deal of disturbing imagery. You can easily see it for yourself with a cursory search engine lookup.
Pictures of babies taped to tables with stacks of cash behind them.
Kids wearing shirts emblazoned with the logo “Pizza Slut”. Comments by
Alefantis and his employees, including “#hotard”, adorned the pictures.
Alefantis’ instagram profile picture was (and still is) an image of
Antinous, the greek boy sex slave of Emperor Hadrian from ancient
legend. All of this is verifiable by using a search engine to look up
images tagged “James Alefantis Instagram”. Though some have alleged that
these images are fake and do not originate from his Instagram account, Alefantis has never denied the images’ authenticity, and in fact has confirmed their legitimacy on camera in an interview he did outside his restaurant with several picketing ‘conspiracy theorists’.
5.>
Alefantis immediately reached out to the media for support against the
defamation of his character by the crazy conspiracy theorists who took
issue with the contents of his Instagram page. Major newspapers
including the Washington Post ran articles defending Alefantis as the
innocent victim of insane kooks run amok. None of the articles made an
issue out of the contents of the Instagram account or of Alefantis’
connections with John Podesta. Nobody thought to say, “Gee, Mr. Alefantis, it seems like maybe your family friendly pizza restaurant shouldn’t have a child sex theme if you want people to not get the impression that you’re running a sex shop out if it.”
6.>
Not a single newspaper, radio, or television show anywhere in the
Western world had a reporter on staff apparently willing to look into
the matter critically, by, say, spending 45 seconds doing a search
engine lookup on Alefantis’ Instagram. With one exception. Ben Swann of
CBS did a five-minute television news segment about Pizzagate where he
mentioned this issue. Ben Swann had been an award-winning journalist
with a history of doing slightly fringe newscasts. Within a week, his
social media accounts were cancelled, and Swann was pulled off the air.
Excitable
‘conspiracy theorists’ are not always well known for their restraint,
and some have badly overreached in their attempts to prove that there’s a
secret dungeon underneath Comet Ping Pong or what not. This is a
tenuous claim, and thus is low-hanging fruit for debunkers who want to
sweep all this stuff under the rug and pretend it doesn’t exist. But the
fact that tenuous claims have been advanced and falsified around the
‘pizzagate’ narrative should not serve as the straw man that allows one
to dismiss the information provided in this article out of hand. The
facts presented here are just that, and the only claim I am making is
the one they seem to support: that these are weird, disturbing pictures
for a politically connected businessman to have associated with his
family-friendly pizza restaurant.
So,
look. This is a deep rabbit hole. Ted Gunderson was a lauded and
accomplished FBI agent who late in life made it a mission to spread the
word about satanist child molesters operating through the alphabet
agencies of the United States Government. The Jeff Ganon story during
the W Bush years hinted at a massive behind-the-scenes sex trade. During
the Reagan years a story broke about a White House sex ring… a story
which quickly vanished.
I’ve
already alluded to the Jimmy Savile case. Every so often a woman will
go on a talk show and discuss her background as a victim of ritualistic
sex abuse, and then never be heard from again. Usually any mention of
“satan worship” brings the bible thumpers out of the woodwork, leaving
most modern sophisticates to conclude that this is the delusion of
fundie Christian nutbars, and pay it no further mind.
My
contention is that the astute observer will have noticed that the
persistence of this rumour, and the trail of verifiable cases which
appear to have broken through to the surface world, hints at a
terrifying truth, most significantly because the breadth and scope of
it, were it to be true, should leave us with serious questions about how
we could be so blind as to be letting this happen right in plain sight.
I
can point to any number of examples in history when the nobility got
carried away with satisfying debauched appetites. The French nobility
comes to mind. Roman orgies come to mind. What makes anyone think human
nature has changed that much? And should we suppose that the war
profiteers who bomb other countries as part of their business model have
healthy personal interests and appetites?
What
I’m trying to do is point out that what may at first seem like an
implausible idea is in fact entirely plausible. In all honesty, you
shouldn’t need training in critical thinking to put two and two together
based solely on the information I’ve just provided to you. When a guy
is posting pedo images on social media and then yelling foul when he’s
called out on it, you are really on the wrong side of history to be
defending his virtue. And of course, Alefantis’ putative guilt in this
matter isn’t by itself sufficient evidence of a worldwide conspiracy of
evildoers. I want to be very clear on this. But we also need to consider
that the deafening silence of the sockpuppet corporatist mainstream
“media” sources on this very alarming issue most certainly is indicative
of a cover-up of sorts on a large scale. These facts I have presented
are, I want to reiterate, not obscure or hard to discern. Everything is
right there in plain sight for any journalist worth his or her salt to
bring to our attention. So why are major publications like The
Washington Post instead intent on defending Alefantis’ honour? These are
questions one should ponder at length.
If
you just can’t get your head around it, well, ok. I couldn’t either for
a long time. There are people who couldn’t come to terms with OJ
Simpson being a murderer. They wanted x to be true, so could not be
convinced that it wasn’t. Once I realized I was making the same mistake,
I began to have second thoughts about this stuff.
The
difference, really, is that in the former case, nobody’s affected by
our silence or misinformed opinion. In this case, presumably, innocent
children are suffering horribly partly because of our collective refusal
to see the facts, admit to them, engage with them, and backtrack on our
falsified narratives. That means that despite this being a horrible,
ugly thing to contemplate, we are morally obligated, it seems to me, to
contemplate it.
The
good news is that a lot of people are aware that this is taking place,
and are involving themselves in the fight to get the word out. I would
encourage you to search your own soul, think hard about the issue, and
see if there’s anything that you can do. We all want the world to be a
better place. I’m not sure myself how to bring that vision to life… but
if the world is, as it appears to be, being run by horribly corrupt
soulless psychopaths who literally worship the mythological incarnation
of evil, maybe getting them out of the way would be an important first
step.
What do you think?
Labels:
comet ping pong,
conspiracy theory,
james alefantis,
jimmy savile,
john podesta,
pizzagate,
satanism,
wikileaks
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)